Leading Ethical Positions


   As we have seen, abortion is a complex moral issue with psychological, social, medical, and political dimensions. In the heat of debate the basic ethical considerations are sometimes lost. Communication between the opposing groups rarely gets beyond the shouting stage. It is therefore necessary to clarify the basic ethical issues at stake, which we will do by surveying three major positions held in America today: abortion "on demand"; abortion "on indication"; and abortion "only to save the life of the mother." This chapter will outline the main lines of argument that characterize these representative positions. In chapter four, after examining the biblical evidence in detail, we will critically evaluate the various positions.

Abortion "On Demand"

   A notable representative of the abortion "on demand" position is Joseph Fletcher, widely known author of Situation Ethics: The New

End of Page 9 - Begin Page 10

Morality, and professor of medical ethics at the University of Virginia School of Medicine. Professor Fletcher's books and articles in professional journals are widely read in the American medical community and have had considerable influence there. In a recent book, The Ethics of Genetic Control, Fletcher discusses abortion in connection with recent issues arising in genetics and medicine, such as artificial insemination, sperm banking, and cloning.[1] He observes that changing attitudes toward human sexuality and the development of modern contraceptive devices have largely separated sexual activity from procreation:

Technology, whether of the "hard" physical kind or the "soft" biological kind, is man's creation and man's hallmark.....Love making and baby making have been divorced. Sex is free from the contingencies and complications of reproduction, and sexual practice can now proceed on its own merits as an independent value in life...."Make love, not people." This is the rock-bottom fact of the new age and the new morality." [2]

Seen in that light, abortion represents one of the many technological means for controlling natural processes such as human procreation, in deference to personal values such as individual freedom and self-fulfillment. Modern man has learned increasingly to subdue the natural order through science and technology, and now modern contraceptive devices and abortion techniques extend such technological control to the biological dimensions of human life and procreation.

   Fletcher's position on abortion embodies a pragmatic approach to moral reasoning. Decisions are made not on the basis of a priori moral principles, but on the basis of a rational calculation of the probable consequences of a given line of action:

....there are in the end only two ways of deciding what is right. Either we will obey a rule (or a ruler) of conscience, which is the a priori or prejudiced approach, or we will look as reasonably as we can at the facts and calculate the consequences, the human costs and benefits — the pragmatic way.....Most of us decide for or against things on the principle of proportionate good. We try to figure out the gains and losses that would follow from one course of action or another and then choose the one

Page 11

that is best, the one that offers the most good. This calculation of consequences is often called a trade-off or cost benefit analysis. [3]

In Fletcher's view, a priori rules must not take precedence over specific calculations of probable costs and benefits to people in the concrete ethical situation. Moral principles may provide useful guidelines for ethical reflection, but they should not be understood as absolutely binding in every circumstance. Under certain circumstances it may be legitimate and morally right to violate widely held moral rules, e.g., rules prohibiting adultery and the taking of innocent human life, if a greater personal good would result. [4]

   Fletcher's cost-benefit approach does recognize that the critical issue is the status of the human being developing in the womb. "The most basic issue is whether a fetus is a person or not."[5] If costs and benefits are to be calculated with the interests of all the persons involved, then the personhood of the unborn must be resolved in some fashion. Fletcher observes that there are three predominant views concerning human personhood: the identification of personhood with biological life, beginning at fertilization; the identification of personhood with the soul, either at the time of conception or at some discrete point thereafter; and the identification of personhood with the rational functions of human personality.

   Fletcher opts for the third alternative: "Humans without some minimum of intelligence or mental capacity are not persons, no matter how many of their organs are active, no matter how spontaneous their living processes are."[6] In Fletcher's view, a score of, say, 20 on the Binet scale of I.Q. would be a minimum criterion of personhood. "Obviously," he notes, "a fetus cannot meet this test, no matter what its stage of growth."[7] The most sensible position, he believes, is to hold that the unborn become persons at birth, when the umbilical cord is cut and the lungs begin to function.[8] Since on this basis the woman is understood to have full personal status and the developing child none, abortion at any stage of pregnancy becomes justifiable whenever the cost-benefit calculation indicates that it would be in the woman's own interests.

   Fletcher recognizes the difficulty of evaluating the competing claims about the personhood of the unborn in a pluralistic society.

Page 12

He maintains that the only possible way of evaluating such claims is a pragmatic one:

The only possible moral test of these rival views lies in their consequences. When beliefs or nonempirical opinions, neither of them being falsifiable, contradict or clash with each other, the only possible way to choose between them morally is in terms of their consequences if they are followed out logically in practice. The one which results in greater good for people is the correct one. On this basis there is an open and shut case for abortion. Obvious and overwhelming, it can be justified very often, sometimes for reasons of human health, sometimes for reasons of human happiness. [9]

To Fletcher's way of thinking, the view that personhood is present from conception not only is empirically unverifiable, but also would cause more harm than good for society. Consequently, it should not be the basis for social policy. The only reasonable policy, he asserts, is to put an end to compulsory pregnancy. "The ethical principle is that pregnancy when wanted is a healthy process, pregnancy when not wanted is a disease — in fact, a venereal disease. The truly ethical question is not whether we can justify abortion but whether we can justify compulsory pregnancy."[10] Thus, having decided to view the unborn as nonpersons, Fletcher concludes that the freedom to abort is desirable both as a personal ethic and as a public policy.

Abortion "On Indications"

   While few evangelicals support abortion "on demand," many argue that certain medical or social circumstances provide justifiable grounds for abortion. An important representative of this perspective in evangelical circles is Professor Norman Geisler of Dallas Theological Seminary, who articulates his position in the widely used textbook, Ethics: Alternatives and Issues. [11]

   Geisler begins by making a careful distinction between contraception and abortion: contraception is an attempt to prevent life from beginning; abortion, a much more serious matter, is an attempt to take life after it has already begun.[12] But is abortion the moral equivalent of murder? Geisler thinks not and points to Exodus 21:22

Page 13

as scriptural support for this view: "When men strive together, and hurt a woman with child, so that there is a miscarriage, and yet no harm follows, the one who hurt her shall be fined....."[13] According to this reading of the text, the capital penalty was to be inflicted for the death of the mother, but not for the death of the child in the womb. On this view, the Mosaic law did not consider an unborn child to be a person in the full sense of the word. Such a view permits one to weigh the value of the actual life of the mother against the value of the potential life of the unborn child when there appears to be an inescapable conflict between the two.

   Geisler's position grew out of an ethical framework he calls hierarchicalism. It holds that there are many universally valid moral norms, and these can be arranged in a hierarchical fashion. In the case of a tragic conflict between two moral norms, the higher norm (e.g., preserving innocent human life) takes precedence over the lower norm (e.g., telling the truth). Thus, when Rahab the harlot lied to protect the Israelite spies [Joshua 2], she chose not the lesser of two evils, but a positively right course of action. The hierarchical approach makes it possible for the Christian to choose a positive good in any situation, no matter how tragic the circumstances.

   As it applies to abortion, the hierarchical understanding affirms as a matter of principle that "an actual person is of more value that a potential person":

....just as the actual plant is more valuable than the seed (potential plant), so a mother is more intrinsically valuable as a person than the fertilized ovum within her womb. For the mother is an actual person, whereas the embryo is only a potential person. She is a mature, free, autonomous subject; the unborn has only the potential to become such. Hence, it would follow that when there are irresolvable conflicts between the values involving potential humans and actual humans, the actual should take precedence over the potential. [14]

This distinction between "actual" and "potential" personhood is based on a view of personhood in which qualities such as self-awareness, self-determination, and the capacity for interpersonal relationships are the determining factors. Since the unborn only exhibit these qualities to a very limited degree, they must be

Page 14

considered potential rather than actual persons.

   Geisler is careful to point out that the hierarchical view does not imply that the developing child is of no value, or that abortion on demand is justified. "An unborn baby is a work of God which He is building into His own likeness. It is a being with increasing value as it develops."[15] Geisler cites Psalm 139:13-15, which speaks of God's providential care for developing human life, as evidence that the Bible does not consider the embryo to be simply an expendable piece of human tissue. Abortion is a very serious moral matter, much more serious than birth control. "Since God is the Author of life, it is a serious thing to stamp out a life which He has permitted to come to pass......Conception is a prima facie case in favor of giving the undeveloped person a chance to develop. One must have some higher moral duty which demands abortion before he initiates it." [16]

   When, then, in Geisler's view, is abortion morally justifiable? He cites three fairly well-defined cases: when the life of the mother is at stake; when the birth would result in a sub-human and not merely deformed or retarded being; and in cases of pregnancy due to rape or incest. "When it is a clear-cut case of either taking the life of the unborn baby or letting the mother die, then abortion is called for."[17] In such a case the actual life of the mother is of more value than the potential life of the unborn child. Geisler deals with a possible objection to this position, which can be posed in the following manner: Might some potential humans not be more valuable than some actual human beings? A future Albert Schweitzer than a drunken harlot? While acknowledging such a possibility, Geisler argues that basing a decision on such considerations would require an omniscience possessed by God alone. Finite human beings must decide on the basis of knowledge available to them. [18]

   In his discussion of anticipated birth defects, Geisler distinguishes between cases of deformity or retardation, and cases that are "sub-human". Only in the latter would "therapeutic" abortion be justified. Specifically, ".....handicaps do not destroy one's humanity. In fact, they often enhance the truly human characteristics in both the handicapped and those who work with them."[19] Anticipated birth defects usually do not constitute grounds for abortion. Many are minor or surgically correctable, and the

Page 15

deformed are still human and capable of interpersonal relations. "The handicapped are human and have the right to life. Abortion thwarts this right in advance." [20]

   Rape and incest, as Geisler acknowledges, raise difficult questions. Is a mother obligated to give birth to a child conceived in rape? Geisler cautiously answers no. "Birth is not morally necessitated without consent......A violent intrusion into a woman's womb does not bring with it a moral birthright for the embryo."[21] But what of the objection that the embryonic human being has a right to life irrespective of the circumstances of conception? In such cases, Geisler argues, the "rights to life, health, and self-determination — i.e., the rights to personhood — of the fully human mother take precedence over that [sic] of the potentially human embryo."[22] Cases of incestuous conception may involve both rape and genetic considerations and hence, he feels, "may provide an even firmer basis for a justifiable abortion." [23]

   There are other cases where, in Geisler's view, abortion is clearly not justified. For example, an unplanned pregnancy where the baby is unwanted does not constitute grounds for abortion. Consent to intercourse implies consent to conception. "Since marriage is automatic consent to intercourse [1 Cor. 7:3ff.].....the children conceived are automatically willed whether they are wanted or not......In brief, any child born of intercourse by consenting parties is implicitly willed and as such has the right to live." [24]

   Neither should abortion be considered as a "back up" to other means of birth control. Once the choice to have intercourse has been made, it is too late to refuse responsibility for the child that may be conceived. Furthermore, given the ready availability of other means of fertility control, there is no need to resort to the morally unjustifiable practice of abortion. [25]

   Geisler touches upon the problem areas of grave threats to mental health, socioeconomic distress, and teenage pregnancies out of wedlock, but without extensive discussion. He concludes that when all the relevant factors are taken into account, abortion may be justified in such cases. Such circumstances would call for Geisler's basic hierarchical framework, where the value of the child's potential life is balanced against the mother's actual life. "All the facts must be

Page 16

weighed and the higher value pursued. The problem is not basically a moral one . . . but a factual one, i.e., determining as a matter of fact which course of action will realize this higher value." [26]

   Geisler's "hierarchical" approach thus represents a fairly sophisticated and discriminating attempt to balance the interests of both mother and unborn child when they appear to conflict. We will evaluate this type of approach, and its exegetical and philosophical foundations, after we have examined the biblical data in chapter four.

Abortion "Only to Save the Life of the Mother"

   A third major position, and one that is widely held in evangelical circles, is that abortion is morally justified only in those infrequent situations where the life of the mother would be threatened by the continuation of the pregnancy. Such an eventuality would arise, for example, in the case of a tubal pregnancy or cancerous uterus. In such a case, if nothing were done, both mother and child would be in danger of perishing. Thus a therapeutic abortion is performed to save a life that has some real prospects of survival.

   A recent expression of this position by an evangelical theologian is found in Death Before Birth, by professor Harold O.J. Brown, formerly of Trinity Evangelical Divinity School.[27] Professor Brown was also instrumental in organizing the Christian Action Council, an evangelical Protestant pro-life organization. The core of the argument contained in Death Before Birth involves his interpretation of several key biblical passages, the use of data concerning prenatal development, and a critique of the utilitarian ethical framework often found in other positions.

   Brown is aware that the Bible does not contain an explicit prohibition of abortion. He observes, however, that neither does the Bible contain explicit prohibitions of infanticide, genocide, or, for that matter, suicide. Such specific prohibitions were unnecessary in view of the biblical prohibition against taking innocent human life. The crucial question is whether the Bible considers the developing fetus to be human life. "If the developing fetus is shown to be a human being, then we do not need a specific commandment against feticide any more than we need something specific against uxoricide (wife killing).

Page 17

The general command against killing covers both." [28]

   Brown argues that the burden of proof in the debate over the humanity of the fetus rests with the pro-abortionist:

With regard to the morality of killing a developing fetus, it is not enough to say that we are not sure it is human. We must be able to say we are sure it is not human. If a hunter were to see movement in a bush and shoot at it, it would not be enough for him to say he was not sure it was not another hunter. He would have to be able to say he was sure it was not. How can we be sure the fetus is not a human being? Clearly, we can not; it is far easier to be sure of the contrary, that it is. [29]

Brown is convinced that an agnostic position regarding the personal status of the developing fetus will not do. A responsible decision requires some credible basis for settling the question of humanity, since, at the very least, potential human life is at stake. Brown observes that although the Bible does not contain a technical or philosophical definition of "human being" or "person", it significantly ".....does not make a principled distinction between the child after birth and in the womb."[30] The Hebrew word yeled, used of children generally, is also used of children in the womb in Exodus 21:22. The Greek word brephos is used in Acts 7:19 to refer to the young Hebrew children slaughtered at Pharaoh's command, and in Luke 1:41,44 to refer to John the Baptist while still in his mother's womb. This usage suggests that the biblical writers saw a continuity between the prenatal and postnatal states.

   The biblical concept of the image of God [Gen. 1:27] is central to the Bible's teaching concerning the dignity and value of human life, according to Brown. Because man is made in God's own image, the shedding of innocent blood pollutes a land and cries out to God for judgment [Num. 35:33]. "If a nation permits the slaughter of the innocent, it surely will bring God's judgment upon itself," warns the author. [31]

   But can we be sure that the image of God is present before birth? Brown argues that if God relates in a personal way to a human creature, that is evidence that the image of God is present. "And," says Brown, "it is abundantly evident from Scripture that God relates to us and is personally concerned for us before birth."[32] He cites Psalm

Page 18

139:13,14, Jeremiah 1:5, Luke 1:44, and Psalm 51:5 as evidence:

For thou hast possessed my reins: thou hast covered me in my mother's womb. I will praise thee; for I am fearfully and wonderfully made; marvelous are thy works; and that my soul knoweth right well [Psalm 139:13,14].

Before I formed thee in the belly I knew thee; and before thou camest forth out of the womb I sanctified thee, and I ordained thee a prophet unto the nations [Jeremiah 1:5].

For, lo, as soon as the voice of thy salutation sounded in mine ears, the babe leaped in my womb for joy [Luke 1:44].

Behold, I was shapen in iniquity, and in sin did my mother conceive me [Psalm 51:5].

On the basis of such texts, Brown concludes that "there can be no doubt that God clearly says the unborn child is already a human being, made in the image of God and deserving the protection of the law."[33] Without involving himself in detailed questions about the precise moment at which the image of God appears during prenatal development, Brown concludes that the biblical data strongly opposes the present abortion climate in America.

   Brown also argues for the humanity of the unborn child on scientific grounds. He notes that even medical authorities who favor abortion have candidly admitted the scientific evidence for the humanity of the unborn. An editorial in the journal California Medicine stated that the "very considerable semantic gymnastics which are required to rationalize abortion as anything but the taking of human life would be ludicrous if not often put forth under socially impeccable auspices."[34] There is no medical or scientific doubt, Brown argues, that the fetus is a human being with a unique chromosomal identity — except in the case of identical twins, where this genetic individuality exists at least from implantation, several days after conception. "Admittedly, there may be some dispute as to precisely when fetal life is 'fully human,' but everyone knows it is a long time before birth, and the Supreme Court permits abortions right up to the moment of birth."[35] Even if one were to adopt a definition of "humanness" in terms of brain waves, which appear at some point during the first trimester — and Brown does not advocate doing so — America would

Page 19

still have to account for hundreds of thousands of homicides each year. [36]

   In Brown's view, the ethical framework for the pro-abortion stance is a pragmatic and utilitarian one:

Make no mistake: the fundamental argument for abortion on demand is pragmatic — it works. The end justifies the means. And the end is utilitarian: the greatest good for the greatest number. In any abortion decision those who will profit from the abortion outnumber the one who will be hurt. The woman will profit, or at least thinks she will. . . . The doctor will profit because he has Medicaid, backed by HEW and the United States taxpayer, to guarantee his bill. [37]

While the principle of "the greatest good for the greatest number" can be valid in situations where proper limits and norms are already established, it cannot function as an ultimate principle overriding the sanctity of human life itself. Brown urges his readers to resist such pragmatic and utilitarian approaches on the basis of a firmly principled ethic based on the biblical teaching of the sanctity of human life made in the image of God. As image bearers of God, human beings have a transcendent dignity and worth irrespective of age, health, or physical beauty. To accept the utilitarian conception of the value of human life presupposed by abortion on demand would, in Brown's view, amount to accepting a most tragic erosion of the very basis of Western civilization.

* * * * * * * * * * * * *

   From this survey of representative ethical positions it has become clear that the key issue in the abortion debate concerns the personal status of the unborn child. Is the developing fetus a "person" in the usual sense of the term? How exactly is the biblical doctrine of the image of God related to the philosophical and legal concept of personhood? Does the Bible clearly indicate that personhood begins at conception, or at some other point during the process of prenatal development? Are the biblical texts cited to prove the personhood of the unborn more than poetic expressions? How do the facts of genetic identity relate to the value judgments made concerning the developing human being? Do the Scriptures indicate that the unborn

Page 20

represent potential human beings or actual human beings?

   In order to establish firm answers to these questions, it will be necessary to make a much more thorough examination of the biblical data than has been made by the writers surveyed thus far. But first, it will be helpful to review some of the factual information available from the medical profession concerning prenatal development, techniques of abortion, and the medical risks of abortion. With that data in hand, the reader will be in a better position to consider the biblical and theological arguments.

Chapter 1  ||  Chapter 3  ||  Table of Contents

1. Joseph Fletcher, The Ethics of Genetic Control (Garden City, N.Y.: Anchor Press, 1974).

2. Ibid., pp.15, 16.

3. Ibid., pp.119, 121.

4. This approach was argued by Fletcher in his earlier work, Situation Ethics: The New Morality (Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1966).

5. Fletcher, Ethics of Genetic Control, p.135.

6. Ibid., p.137.

7. Ibid.

8. Ibid., p.139.

9. Ibid., pp.138, 139.

10. Ibid., p.142. For similar conclusions, cf. Garrett Hardin, Mandatory Motherhood (Boston: Beacon Press, 1974).

11. Norman Geisler, Ethics: Alternatives and Issues (Grand Rapids: Zondervan, 1971). Other writers who hold the "indications" position include Daniel Callahan, Abortion: Law, Choice, and Morality (New York: Macmillan, 1970); R.F.R. Gardner, Abortion: The Personal Dilemma (Old Tappan, N.J.: Fleming H. Revell, 1974; Harmon L. Smith, Ethics and the New Medicine (Nashville: Abingdon Press, 1970).

12. Geisler, Ethics, p.218.

13. The rather complicated questions of translation and interpretation surrounding Exodus 21:22-25 are discussed in some detail in chapter four of this volume. Geisler apparently has not taken fully into account other possible interpretations of this text.

14. Geisler, Ethics, p.118.

15. Ibid., p.219.

16. Ibid., p.220.

17. Ibid.

18. Ibid., p.221.

19. Ibid., p.222. Evidently, Geisler no longer considers Downs Syndrome ("Mongolism") a justification for abortion.

20. Ibid., p.225.

21. Ibid., p.222.

22. Ibid., p.222,223.

23. Ibid., p.223.

24. Ibid., p.224.

25. Ibid., p.225.

26. Ibid., p.226.

27. Harold O.J. Brown, Death Before Birth (Nashville: Thomas Nelson, 1977). Other evangelicals holding this general position include Clifford E. Bajema, Abortion and the Meaning of Personhood (Grand Rapids: Baker, 1974); C. Everett Koop, The Right to Live: the Right to Die (Wheaton: Tyndale House, 1976); C.C. Ryrie, You Mean the Bible Teaches That . . . (Chicago: Moody Press, 1974); Meredith G. Kline, "Lex Talionis and the Human Fetus," Journal of the Evangelical Theological Society 20, no.3 (1977): 193-202; Donald Shoemaker, Abortion, the Bible, and the Christian (Cincinnati: Hayes, 1976); Bruce Waltke, "Reflections from the Old Testament on Abortion," Journal of the Evangelical Theological Society 19, no.1 (1976): 5-13. For an excellent exegetical study, cf. John Frame et al., "Report of the Committe to Study the Matter of Abortion," Agenda, 38th General Assembly, Orthodox Presbyterian Church, 1971, pp.90-110.

This position is also the official position of the Roman Catholic Church. See John T. Noonan, ed., The Morality of Abortion (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1970), pp.1-39; John Connery, Abortion: The Development of the Roman Catholic Perspective (Chicago: Loyola University Press, 1977).

Also representative of this point of view are Baruch Brody, Abortion and the Sancity of Life (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1975); Thomas W. Hilgers and Dennis J. Horan, eds., Abortion and Social Justice (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1972); Paul Ramsey, "The Sanctity of Life: In the First of It," Dublin Review 241 (1967-68): 3-23; Dr. and Mrs. J.C. Willke, Handbook on Abortion (Cincinnati: Hayes, 1975).

28. Brown, Death Before Birth, p.119.

29. Ibid.

30. Ibid., p.120.

31. Ibid., p.122.

32. Ibid., p.126.

33. Ibid., p.127. Some of the criticisms raised against this way of reading the texts, e.g., the objection that such a reading does not take into account the metaphorical language of the Psalms, will be examined in chapter four of this volume.

34. Cited in ibid., p.134.

35. Ibid., p.135.

36. Ibid., p.136.

37. Ibid., pp.146, 147.

Chapter 1  ||  Chapter 3  ||  Table of Contents